Critique of Environmental Ethics and Moral in the 21st century



World Philosophy Congress on the Philosophy of Aristotle, under the Auspices of the President of the Hellenic Republic and with the support of the International Federation of Philosophical Societies (FISP)

ARISTOTLE’S ETHICS

António dos Santos  Queirós

Center of Philosophy of the University of Lisbon

Alameda da Universidade

1600-214 Lisboa   Portugal


Title: Critique of Environmental Ethics and Moral in the 21st century


Abstract
This paper discuss the concepts of modern Ethics and Moral, on a critical perspective to the dominant standpoint that set the morale in the order of the rules and social conventions and leave the ethics on the field of personal experience.
He follows a research line trying to discover the complex and dialectical connection between ethics and moral, from Aristotle's Ethics and Aristotle’s Politics to the contemporary Environmental Philosophy and Environmental Ethics.
This paper analyses the contribution of the environmental philosophy from the twentieth century philosophy renovation and, in this context, the particular contribution from the Portuguese philosophers: the  historical contribution from Bento (Baruch) de Espinosa (born in a Jew Portuguese family); Antero de Quental, Portuguese philosopher from XIX century, that build their Philosophy of Nature on a critical perspective of the thought of Ernest Haëckel; and Jorge de Sena philosophical poet and writer from the XX century, teacher and world citizen in Brazil and USA.
Their analytic perspective is that the fundamental push of environmental philosophy is the ethical issue and the moral problems.
Contrasting with the history of philosophy, that the core problems are the human condition, the environmental philosophy drive their thought to the “raison d 'être”, the sense of the existence of the world and their phenomenology, without becoming a philosophy against the Human being, because the nature of the Human being, the nature of all entities and beings from the universe, is that they was generate by the same "star dust".
Modern "Environmental Reason" emerged, with a new categorical imperative to the men’s action, beyond the Kantian principle conforming individual acts with a universal law, configuring the human conduct within the limits that safeguard the continuity of life and its diversity, a new ethical framework built by Environmental Philosophy.
Our critical essay postulates three fundamental theses:
1. The environmental philosophy builds a new ontology created by the critique of anthropocentrism…2. But, only their articulation with a new epistemology, founded in the critique of ethnocentrism, could lead to a new ethics universal theory. 3. However, the applied ethics of environmental philosophy needs a new global political ethics shaped on the critique against political alienation.
Keywords: Environment, moral, ethics, anthropocentrism, ethnocentrism, alienation
Ethics and Moral
The Wittgenstein's distinction between ethics and moral are common to most contemporary philosophical thought, moral is placed in the order of the rules and social conventions and the ethics is situated in the field of personal experience.
However, if ethics emerges of subjectivity of each individual person, as says Cristina Berckert, does not have universal value.[1]
But why not  inquire this principle and, at the same time, in terms of morals and ethics, their common nature of social product, how singular, autonomous and original it seems the philosophical thought that supports them, without depreciate the specific speech from philosophy? Why oppose so irreducibly subjectivity and universal value? The question is: the existence of universal moral values may or may not be recognized by the subjectivity of each and every human being, like happen with the international law? The environmental values could create a new ethical paradigm, with various ethical practices and new moral conventions subordinated to a global bioethics?
Inquiring those apories leads us to revisit the history of philosophy, not in a chronological logic but in dilemmatic logic.
The compromise "of practical wisdom" of Ricoeur is a real possibility not just because it emanates from two models of action – the theological Aristotelian and the deontological Kantian – only formally separated, but because these models share a common culture and society.
Our perspective is not to replace the philosophical discourse by a sociological analysis or an anthropology study. Philosophical discourse has a specific identity that is distinct from the literary speech or the psychological analysis. But, that don’t means philosophical discourse cannot coexist or cross other speeches, as the arts and politics, and by this way we arrive to the issue of political philosophy.
Ethics and city-state
In Aristotelian teleology, the symbiosis between the ontological, anthropological and ethical levels outcome from human nature, which have in its own nature the virtues of reason to proceed cautiously by the good and achieve happiness (eudaimonia).
The supreme virtue is wisdom (sóphos) which go ahead to contemplation. Prudence raises the man on the condition of the city's ruler and confers them moral superiority because it combines in itself the ethical and political dimension; but contemplation already is from the domain of the divine sphere. The Aristotelian Man is not only a philosophical abstraction, but also a citizen; Aristotle’s thought builds a bridge between two dimension of human being, the philosophy of existence and political philosophy. Aristotle’s human beings are the only species that has not only biological capacities but a “rational soul” as well. Aristotle conceives of ethical theory in order to live in accordance with virtue, one way in which such goods as friendship, pleasure, health…fit together as a whole and in lifelong activities. The rational part of the soul searches the highest good!
We become virtuous on the city community, sharing with parents, citizens and friends the responsibility for acquiring and exercising the virtues.
Aristotle identifies the nature of human being with its end or final cause to the good, in the Physics and in the Eudemian Ethics. For human beings the ultimate good or their natural function consists in walk way to inaccessible perfection.
The Politics postulates the political nature of human beings for living in the city-state.
Aristotle maintains that only on the city-state human beings attains the limit of good life, which means accept the law and justice authority of the community.
On the political context of Aristotle age, different forms of rule are required for citizens and despotic rule for slaves. Disturb those balanced system will results in disorder and injustice. In this political context the main principle of the rule of reason also implies different constitutions for different city-states, justifying tyranny or democracy.
Modernity broken human nature
When the philosophy of Descartes announces its vision of modernity of human thought, that emerges from an autonomous subject who thinks and acts using the reason, the division between the human being and nature not becomes inevitable, they are the result from the dilemmatic choice of the philosopher (s).
If opened the way to study nature as object of science, to discover mechanical laws designed by God in the cosmos, the raise of the man above nature, reigning over all beings and things for the award of the Creator, came from the domain of religion and politics and from the subordination of philosophy to its dogmas and interests. It’s appears in the first flush of mercantilism, as a social necessity. [2]
The moral void, that the Cartesian philosophy does not occupied, it's not inevitable consequence of the abandonment of divine conception of human nature and their ontological, ethical and anthropological unity; even in classical Western philosophy, in parallel with the Aristotelian thought, other concepts of moral emerged without religious foundation, but never becoming dominant.  Such was the case of Epicurus, which work we know only a few fragments, that is singularly modern in its appeal to the altruism in relation to the “other” and concerning the possession of material goods, the practice of gender equality in the gardens of the philosophy and above recognition of the intrinsic meaning of life liberated from the heuristics of fear ... of death.
Or, at the East and China, the morals rules of Confucian and Tao.
The doctrine founded by Confucius advocated the implementation of ethical codes and rituals to guide the community in their conduct and persuade its members to love and respect each other, and to restore the order on the society and on the family, based on a solid hierarchy system. In this moral system, Jen (Compassion) and Yi (compassion), prevail over the Li (interest/benefit).
The philosophical Taoism, a philosophical school based on the texts Dao De Jing (道德 ) attributed to Laozi and Zhuangzi (庄子), and their tian-dao or "nature's way", propose not a moral code but a species of spiritual self-discipline that emphasizes the autonomy of being conscious and its unity with the universal nature and leads the man to act respecting the three Moral Treasures: compassion, moderation, and humility. [3]
Backing to the advent of the modern age, the thought of Bento de Espinosa surmount the dichotomy between the subjectivity and the nature, without breaking that unity; the concept of extension of the categories of God Substance and God Nature, unifies the being and the duty, without putting the Man above nature and under their domain. However not denies the autonomy of reason that Kant would elevate to a higher grade; furthermore, is that potentiality to liberate the power of rationality and human autonomy, on the unity of Substance and Nature, which not consents no one privileged status to the man specie.
And if this singular vision of the human condition precipitated the sectarian and fanatic odium of the Jewish Inquisition, also carried out the thought of Espinosa to our modernity, what means replace the Man outside the anthropocentric sphere, where Western philosophical and religions_­  the Christian, the Jewish and the Muslim,  settle the human being.
The development of modern concept of Nature
The controversy of Antero with Haëckel
Philosophy on the XIX century, the "metaphysical speculation", following Antero de Quental analysis, was in debit to the amazing progress of "natural sciences" and "social sciences", increased by the foundation of new subject areas and new scientific branches, and our philosopher, with humility, recognized their own limited capacity, but also of any other scientist or intellectual from the new epochal, to encompass such a large immensity of knowledge. At the same time, Antero claims that the new philosophy should penetrate, step by step, into the consciousness of his citizen’s fellows and all the Humanity. There is a key passage in the essay Tendências da Filosofia no Século XIX (Tendencies of Philosophy in the 20th century), where this new paradigm emerges in thesis: One of the original ideas of Antero, about the modern concept of nature, opposed to the vulgar opinion, is that the general theory of evolution not emerges as a discovery of natural sciences in the XIX century, but as a result of philosophical speculation.
"…speculative (philosophical) elaboration, since three centuries, was projected in the field of science." [4]
Following Antero and the critique of Aristotle’s Philosophy:
"… from the Renaissance, inside the fundamental idea of nature. The dynamic way, autonomous, realistic, of conceiving nature is what more radically distinguishes the modern (philosophical) thought from the old thought... (our parenthesis between and underline)
The critique of anthropocentrism
We can finally focused our attention in an historical and unknown fact: Antero and their companions of the Portuguese 70 Generation (XIX century), analyzed and evaluated the philosophy of nature proposed by Ernest Haëckel[5]; this "philosopher" and the "naturalist" Ernest Haëckel are the same people, internationally recognized as the founder of modern Ecology. [6]
What Antero critique in Haëckel thought, as we saw earlier, is that ignore "... the importance of the idea of finality ..." and "... The horror puerile to metaphysics ... ", which is considered by Antero the primary source of construction and evolution of modern scientific thought ( and philosophy)”. (our parenthesis between)
And what share with the creator of Ecology and their scientific contribution to found the Environmental Ethics, is the critique of the principle of anthropocentrism. Haëckel himself, evoked as concetor of Ecology Science, is ignored as precursor of environmental philosophy and even linked to racism, from their thesis "ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny".
So, is necessary making a brief review of his thought, limited to the themes under analysis, focused on their original books.
In the work The Enigmas of the Universe, Haëckel note the importance of the "law of substances" completed by the "theory of evolution", like the keys of the enigma, because the permanence of energy and matter in the universe explaining its evolution, constituting the essence of monistic philosophy. His philosophical and scientific matrix was built, at the time, from the premonitory work of Goethe about the Metamorphosis of Plants (1799), the theory of the environment in determining the adaptations of all types of organisms of the philosopher and French naturalist Lamarck (1809) and the theory of evolution by Charles Darwin (1859).
In the History of the Creation of Beings Organised According to the Laws of Nature emerges a clear critique of anthropocentrism, in the context of the defense of "scientific materialism and morality":
"... first the geocentric error, which made the Earth the center of the world, around which turn the Sun, the Moon and the stars; after the error anthropocentric, which considers the human being as the Supreme and preferred end of creation, the being to which all other nature was created. These two mistakes were put down, the first by the coperniana world system theory, in the early of 16th century; the second by the genealogical theory of Lamarck, in the early of 19th century. "[7]  (our underline)
 From those fundamental theses, answer Haëckel to the "... great enigma of the universe: ' the place of the man in nature" and the question of its “natural origin ".
As scientist Haëckel symbolize the 19th century progress of the knowledge of nature and human nature, the biology with the cell theory, physics, with the optics and acoustics, the theory of magnetism and electricity, the mechanics and the theory of heat, the physics of stars and the chemistry,  revealing the carbon as “the basis of life chemistry” and allowing to discovery:
"... that the same materials that make up our planet and living beings that inhabit are also those who make up the mass of other planets, the Sun and the stars more distant." [8]
And so ...
 "... the unity of forces of nature in the universe ... the law of substances as ' fundamental ' cosmological law". [9]
Along the cited work we can find a global critique to the anthropocentric philosophy. Not only the critique against the anthropocentric dogma, which conceives God as the image of man, and the “anthropological” dogma, generator of duality body-decomposable versus soul-immortal.
Concluding about the ethical imperative to "renounce this unacceptable illusion of grandeur" that placed man as absolute ruler of nature.
Analyzing the relationship between philosophy and natural sciences, on the light of controversy among philosophers and naturalists, invokes Schiller and calls every one to search the truth, stating the need of convergence of the heritage of the idealist philosophy, from Plato and Hegel and the realistic philosophy of Bacon and Mill, concluding:  
"The exclusive supremacy granted to empiricism is a mistake no less harmful than the opposite error which gives supremacy to speculation." [10]
At this point that philosophy makes an approach to the thought of Antero de Quental. It's not the scope of this paper to examine the thought of Haëckel in all philosophical, scientific and political dimensions. But we cannot fail to point out, in our context of research, the defense of a Pantheism inspired by Bento de Espinosa, the relationship, citing Humboldt, between monistic philosophy and naturalist art, particularly the painting of landscape, not only in the aspect of scientific representation but also in their intellectualizing and spiritualization, which leads to theorize the "modern love by nature" as a source of aesthetic pleasure and  ethics elevation of human being, when he recognizes the sense of things and its relationship with the other parts of nature, wonder, bewilderment and stupor.
"... which are together elements of our soul life’s’ that are integrated under the name of natural religion." [11]
And so proclaims, about the present and future life:
"Our monism teaches us that we are children of the Earth, mortals who will not have more than one, two or more than three ' generations ', to enjoy in this life the splendors of our planet, to contemplate the inexhaustible wealth of its beauty and enjoy the wonderful game of its forces." [12]
One last note about the stigma of racist, declare against the philosophy of Haëckel. If their conceptions about the “laws of natural selection” led them to reject contemporary ideals of socialism, is sure that argued for equality between men and women, recognizing their equal value and dignity, and himself, with remarkable lucidity politics, makes distance from her future detractors:
"We do not underestimate the risk that exists to carry so brutally scientific theories to the domain of political practice. The complex conditions of our civilization require to the man dedicated to the policy activates a cautiousness so enlightened, a strong historic preparation, a critical sense so delicate, that does not permit applied such a ' natural law ' to the practice of social life, otherwise under the largest reserve." [13]
The “environmental reason”: critique of ethnocentrism and critique of anthropocentrism
The struggle to differentiate ethics from morality, that the common sense understand as normative ethics (what we ought to do) from philosophical or meta-ethics (what is the nature of the Good), cannot be exceptionally simple. If normative ethics is something the common people call "ethics", what is the nature and objet of this conceptualization of "ethics” and what is the nature and object of meta-ethics? The modern consensus about the two questions is that ethics emerges of subjectivity of each individual human being and moral is placed in the domain of the rules and social conventions. We are in disagreement with those dominant theses.
First, analyzing this conceptual construction, on the light of environmental philosophy, we must interrogate ourselves if we stay in the framework of the anthropocentrism or not!?
Second, Moral, in our view, is a cultural expression determined by social dominance and historical context, who gives them a sectary and transitory character. We needs a moral theory (that I call ethics) that could be universal, transtemporal (project in the present and in the future)  and available to light human individual conduct and the human science as well as their political ideologies and practices, without considering  man as the final zenith of Life.
The opposition between individual ethics-universal ethics, universal ethics- moral contingents is something that needs to be transcended. Where others see antagonism, we glimpse a complex dialectic.
The environmental reason
The "environmental reason" formulates a new categorical imperative for human action, beyond the Kant maximum of forming individual ethics of acts with the principle of a universal law, a new ethical framework, which stems from the need to configure the human conduct within the limits that safeguard the continuity of life and its diversity.[14] .
The environmental reason creates its own ethical principles and applied ethics, based on the critique of anthropocentrism and the critique of ethnocentrism.
On the basis of these two negative axioms she incorporates new moral concepts,  from Land Ethics  and Animal Ethics, which extend the concept of community to all beings of nature and extend the concept of person, at least to animals that have capacity to feel and suffer, in particular of those who are closest to us in the evolutionary chain.
The environmental reason also incorporates a Global Bioethics, which relocate the man inside the Nature, but without any privileged status. And attach to the species of  homo sapiens the higher moral value  ( and responsibility), for his paradoxical ability to create and destroy biodiversity. 
The environmental reason recognize to each individual “human being” a status of moral equality between its multiple persons and a unique (ancestral) family: all the people have the same mitochondrial mother and the same chromosomal father. And, one more time according to and beyond modern science, the supreme duties to preserves Life before Man and Earth before Life, what means conserve biodiversity with the man and the abiotic factors of life. 
The environmental reason also includes a new Political Ethics and a new critical view of alienation of citizens. A new Political Ethics policy that elaborated the principle of common home“… the man has two homelands, his own and planet Earth”[15], founding a new international order (ethics and political order) with the principle of planetary Community and planetary solidarity, the basis of the principles of sustainability, solidarity and equity. A Political Ethics with two new categorical imperatives, the “imperative of the dignity” and “the imperative of perpetual peace” which goes far beyond the Kantian concept of peace.
Let us then to develop the genesis and the maturation of the concept of environmental reason.
From the conservationist paradigm of Nature to the concept of Environment.
The new ethics
We conceptualize “environment” as the concept that expresses the relationship between nature and culture, in the complexity and diversity of the cultural landscape _ urban and rural landscape, fully humanized and wilderness (with less human influence). Including in the concept of cultural landscape its material and immaterial heritage, their cultural expression and forms, their immeasurable emotional relationship with the countless human beings who have been born and shaped them, becoming too transformed. [16]
The critique of environmental philosophy queries our civilization mode, in the perspective of environmental reason. Nature shall be included in our field of moral reflection. Our duties, before limited to human beings, must be expanded to the domains of the “Land Ethic” and “Animal Ethics”.
The Land Ethics: enlarging le concept of community
The principle of community of Aristotle has focused on the city-state, because the human good life depends on the community not only for material necessities but also for moral education and civic education; and the classic dilemma of human perfection-worst animal (without laws and justice), returns to the modern framework of ethics and moral, with a new significance, a new object of justice, and new rules face nature.
All human ethics theories are based on a premise: that the person is a member of an interdependent community:
“…The land ethic simply enlarges the boundaries of the community to include soils, water, plants, and animals, or, collectively: the land “[17]
Animal Ethics: enlarging le concept of person
Principle of perfection of Aristotle understands good and evil in terms of an anthropocentric teleology. However too recognizes that is a good when nature operates for one's good of an end, like the animals natural behavior.
Australian Peter Singer and American T. Regan emphasizing the feelings and the rights of animals face the brutality of modern production processes: genetic cloning, cages, feedstuffs based on ground meat from dead animals and saturated hormones, systematic violation of natural rhythms and needs of animal life, all this in terms of maximum profit. Invoking the principle of equality, the two authors refuse the concept of the superiority of the human species that compare to racism, for violating that principle, censoring to the human beings the non-recognition of the capacity of feeling and suffering of animals. In their works they claim that animals are subjects of interest by not suffering and also, add Regan, are subjects of law, are subjects of a life experience that has intrinsic value. Departing from this approach they propose extend the concept of person:
“I propose the use of 'person' to beings rational and self-conscious, to incorporate the elements of the common sense of human being that are not covered by member of species Homo Sapiens“. [18]
Based on the thesis that "... some non-human animals appear to be rational and aware of himself, conceiving itself as distinct beings that have a past and a future...", proposes a gradualist ethics against the killing of animals, which in its upper level extends to chimpanzees, gorillas and orangutans the same protection due to human beings.
The principles of "common home" and "community and planetary solidarity"
From the first UN environmental conferences, held in Stockholm in 1972, emerged the principle of a “common house” "… man has two homelands, his own and planet Earth"; the principle of a planetary community and solidarity, founders of a new international order (political and ethical order) and the principle of defending life on the planet and its biodiversity before humanism.
Those principles build a first frontier line with the cultural and political perspective of ethnocentrism.
The ethical imperative of dignity and the imperative of peace, from Kant to Jorge de Sena
Antero de Quental, in the end of XIX century, claims for the advent of a new art, more universal, having the music as a paradigm; It is therefore natural that the poetic literary nourish also the new philosophy in the XX century.
The world of Kant is not our world. The philosophical and practice dimension of the problems assumes now a tragic magnitude. In our historical and environmental context, humanity is confronted for the first time with the danger of its own extinction, as a result of environmental disaster or as the tragic outcome of a biological or nuclear war; structural unemployment, new pandemics and major famines occur on multiple continents, as a consequence of economy globalization and financial crises.
“The imperative ethical of dignity”, from Jorge de Sena ( Portuguese writer), proclaims the ethical principle and moral that, we (persons, nations, entrepreneurs, governments…) ought to live be sure that nobody is less alive, or suffer or dies to benefice our quality of life and life time. .
Poem: “Letter to my kids about the shootings of Goya”
…Believe me that no world, that nothing or no one
is more worth than a life, or the joy of having it.
This is what is the most important - this joy.
Believe that the dignity they will tell you so much about
is nothing but that joy that comes
from being alive and knowing that anytime someone
is less alive or suffers or dies
so that one of you can resist a little more
to the death that belongs to all and will come…”[19] (our underline)
The absolute value of life face the absolute lost of the end of life, give to the ( limited) time of life an ethical dimension (“the joy of life”) that nothing and nobody can ignore; and establish a gradualistic morality : Act so that you treat another person and humanity (and nations) without no less life ( the oppose of a full life), no suffer, not damages that anticipate or bring the die. “The ethical imperative of dignity”!
 And if associated to the critique of anthropocentrism, we can extend this categorical imperative to Life and Earth.
Jorge de Sena, also rethink the Kant’s imperative of “perpetual peace”, choosing the theme of the nuclear bomb and the connection between peace and liberty.
Poem: “Peace”
“…In the strange fortune of doom,
[...] this strange fortune, from which light comes
oh just harmless powder, I pray
to myself not to lose the memory,
for you, always know how to remember
that everything is lost where peace is lost,
and first of all freedom is lost… “[20]
The categorical “imperative of perpetual peace” try to answer to the global crisis that liberal democratic or socialist politics and their economies and markets failed to overcome and the blind science also promoted. 
Practical ethics and political alienation
In the XIX century Feuerbach and Marx focused the debate about the concept of alienation on the religion issue. Feuerbach’s analysis postulates that belief in religion was an intellectual error that could be correct by education. Marx’s criticizes Feuerbach to fail understanding why people fall into religious alienation. Marx’s thesis was that religion is a response to alienation in material life; their main corollary was the struggle for changing material life, the pathway to emancipate human consciousness from all alienation.
Lukács' understanding alienation as a historical loss of totality that we can already find on the historical trajectory of institutions of social life, creating a “second nature” were the individual person can´t find the world meaning. When Lukács applies this concept to the history of intellectual representation, looking to the Grecian movement from epic poetry to tragedy and then to philosophy, notes that the source of significance became progressively more transcendent to immediate life and individual consciousness. Considering the modernity, he proposes a renewed relation between individual conscience and the knowledge of world where meaning can again be found, rebuilding a new totality, new forms of art and communication.
The possibility to recognize that utopia on a good sense, the unity of the global representation of the word with the citizen consciousness, postulates the opposed possibility, the full alienation of the individual person, manipulated by a global power, economic, political and ideological. The concept of double negation employed by Marcuse is a critical response to negation of personal freedom by an oppressive/repressive socio/economic system and to the development of individual-critical consciousness.
When analyzes the concept of alienation we don’t want obliterate the ontological issue and the philosophical contribution of existentialism, as a plural literary-philosophical phenomenon crossing two centuries. The core of this study is not the fundamental debate about the “meaning of being”_ the paradoxical presence of God, from  Kieergard, the challenge of nihilism, “God is dead,” from Nietzsche, the “Dasein,” (“being that we ourselves are”),  from Heidegger, “the existentialism is a new humanism,” from Sartre…We wants to discuss the political dimension of the human being, and what means the good and the devil, for the moral of XXI century polices.
Utilitarian ethics of Jeremy Bentham and Stuart Mill, assumes that "not only any action of a private individual, but all the Government measures"[21] must improve the well-being and reduce suffering. Far away the primacy of duty (eudainomia) from Aristotle, he based morality of action on benefits back to their subject and/or in the principle of less suffering caused to the "other".
The classic example of resolving an ethical dilemma on the basis of the principle of utilitarianism is the political and moral justification of the launch of the first atomic bomb over Hiroshima, and the second over Nagasaki. This was due to the comparison made by military strategists: if the US chooses to invade and conquer Japan with conventional weapons they estimated there would be one million deaths instead of the more than 200,000 confirmed with the bombings.
The most frequent moral objection against the resolution of this ethical dilemma by nuclear holocaust of the Japanese people lies in the intrinsic value of human life. In the Kantian categorical imperative, this is an end in itself and cannot be used/annihilated as a means to benefit other people, even if to achieve a higher benefit, which in this case is to reduce casualties.
Departing from this framework, it seems that modern ethics and morals seem to be inconsistent in practice and paradoxical in theory.
But in the weeks before the nuclear attack against Hiroshima, most scientists who worked on the development of the atomic bomb, the Manhattan project, tried to prevent the bombing over the Japanese cities, proposing a different strategy: the explosion should take place in open space, in order to demonstrate its destructive power and save innocent life.
Confronted with the hesitance of the leader of the project, the military on charge manipulate information, resorting to threat and blackmail.
After the first, the military comand demanded the second, by arguing that the Japanese militarists wouldn't surrender.
The secret military documents at the time, that are now longer considered classified, show that there was a deliberate intention to try the nuclear weapon effect on humans beings, but also a second purpose: to  the triumphant USSR and of the new socialist States emerging in the East and in Asia: it was the beginning of the Cold War!
Those scientists, conscious of the dangers of the military use of nuclear energy, and of the risks of new clashes that could lead to the extinction of humanity, promoted a civic and political movement called Movement of Scientists. This movement would bring together 515 scientists from Harvard and MIT in 1945, who defended a program that would be the inspiration to all subsequent books, articles and speeches. Their objective was to lead the US Government to an international agreement with the USSR, upon which they would agree that such would no longer be produced. They argue five arguments:
Other Nations would soon be able to produce atomic bombs
No effective defense was possible.
Mere numerical superiority in atomic weaponry offered no security.
A future atomic war would destroy a large fraction of civilization.         
International cooperation of an unprecedented kind is necessary for our survival.
The heuristics of fear was their propaganda strategy, but the US Government managed to dismantle this movement in 1947 and adopted this speech exactly for the opposite end.
This example demonstrates that the practical application of ethics, and ethics practices, needs to be formatted in the context of a new political ethics, and the discussion of ethical dilemmas must be informed by all political facts and bright by the critique of political alienation.
A global polical ethics rooted by the environmental philosophy
The ethical dimension of societies and  modern State and its Governments may be evaluated by the respect for the principles of political ethics, universal and permanent, which recognize all individuals as citizens with two homelands, their own and the Earth (United Nations Conference on the Environment, Stockholm, 1972), to all human cultures a status of equality (critique of ethnocentrism) and re-introducing the human community on the pyramid of life and biodiversity without any status of domain or privilege (critique of anthropocentrism), evaluate especially in times of crisis.
The principles of citizenship or dignity of its citizens and peaceful (political) solution of conflicts (Sena), applied together with the subordination of the economy to the environmental ethics policy, determines the State's duty to guarantee its citizens the right to peace, the right to work, the right to education, the right to health and assistance in old age, the right to access the justice, the right to the conservation of biodiversity and the right to freedom, and yes, freedom is placed in this order, because she disappears with the war and remains a smaller  value  without job, homeless and other social rights. And the consequences of destruction of life diversity would be that human communities have no future.
Without peace, everything will be lost, and firstly, freedom will be lost.
The environmental philosophy built a new ontology from the critique of anthropocentrism, but only their articulation with a new epistemology, founded in the critique of ethnocentrism, could lead to a new theory of universal ethics. .
References
Augustine of Hippo. The City of God. Translation by William Babcock, notes by Boniface Ramsey. Hyde Park, NY: New City Press, 2012
Aristotle. The Complete Works of Aristotle, English Translation, Jowett, Benjamin, The Revised Oxford Translation, vol. 2, ed. Jonathan Barnes. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984.
Assunto, R., Berleant, A., Berque, A., D´Angelo, P., Simmel, G., Veríssimo Serrão, A… “Philosophy of Landscape. An anthology”. Coordination of Adriana Veríssimo Serrão. Centre of Philosophy of the University of Lisbon. Lisboa. 2012
Beckert, Cristina. Ética. CFUL. 2012
Bentham, Jeremy, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. 1907. Library of Economics and Liberty. 31 October 2014
Berleant, A. Changing Landscapes, Keynote lecture at “Transition Landscapes/ Paysages en Transition,” International Conference, Lisbon, Portugal, 2011
Berque, A. L’écoumène, mesure terrestre de L’Homme, mesure humaine de la Terre: pour une problématique du monde ambiant, L’espace géographique 4, 299-305,1993
Callicott. J. Baird. In Defense of tile Land Ethic: Essays in Environmental Philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1989
Camus, Albert. The Stranger. Tr. Matthew Ward. New York: Knopf, 1988 [1942]
Carvalho, Joaquim de Carvalho. Evolução Espiritual de Antero, in Estudos sobre a Cultura Portuguesa do Século XIX_ (I Antheriana), in Obras Completas de Antero de Quental_III, Filosofia, Organização, Introdução e Notas de Joel Serrão. Universidade dos Açores. Lisboa: Edit. Comunicação, 1991
Chuang Tzu. Basic Writings. Translated by Burton Watson. New York: Columbia University Press, 1964
Confucius. The Analects. Lun YÜ. Tramslated with and introduction by D.C. Lau, Preface by A.C. Grayling, London: The Folio Society, 2009
Descartes, René. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch and Anthony Kenny, Cambridge: Cambridge Universiety Press, 3 vols.1984-1991
Dias, Jorge. Estudos de Antropologia, Volume I, Uma introdução histórica à etnografia portuguesa. Published in 1961. Lisboa: Imprensa Nacional-Casa da Moeda, 1990
Épicure. Sentences Vaticanes,  In  Lettres et Maximes,  Trad., Introd. and Notes de Jean-François Balaudé. Paris. Librairie Générale Française, 1994
Espinosa, Bento. Ética. Demonstrada à maneira dos geómetras. Parte I. De Deus. Introdução e Notas de Joaquim Carvalho. Atlântida Editora. Coimbra, 1960
Feuerbach, Ludwig. The Essence of Christianity, translated by George Eliot. Prometheus Books, Penguin Random House, USA, 1989 [1841]
Haeckel, Ernest. Histoire de la Création des Êtres Organisés D'après les Lois naturelles.  Paris: Libraire Germer Bailliére et Cª, 1884
Haeckel, Ernest. Les preuves du Transformisme. Réponse à Virchow.  Paris: C. Reinwald, Libraire-Éditeur, 1882
Haeckel, Ernest. Los Enigmas del Universo. Valência: F. Sempere y Cª Editores.Éditeur, 18…
Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time, trans. by John Macquarie and Edward Robinson. London: SCM Press, 1962
Kant, Immanuel. The Metaphysics of Morals. Trans. Mary Gregor. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996 [1927]
Kant, Immanuel. Toward Perpetual Peace and Other Writings on Politics, Peace, and History.
Edited and with an introduction by Pauline Kleingeld. Translated by David Colclasure. With essays by Jeremy Waldron, Michael W. Doyle, and Allen W. Wood. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2006
Kierkegaard, Søren. Fear and Trembling. Tr. Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983 [1843]
Jonas, Hans. The Imperative of Responsibility. In Search of an Ethics for the technological Age. Chicago. Chicago & London, The University of Chicago Press, 1984
Lao Tse. The Tao Teh King (Taoteching). Charles Johnston, Lao Teh King: An Interpretation of Lao Tse's Book of the Way and of Righteousness. Kshetra Book, U.S, Amazon
Leopold, Aldo. A Sand County Almanac. New York: Oxford University Press, 1949
Lorenz, Konrad. Die acht Todsünden der zivilisierten Manschheit. München/Zürich: Piper, 1973
Lukács, György.  Velha e Nova Cultura [1920]. In Revolución y Antiparlamentarismo, México: Ediciones Pasado y Presente, 1978
Marcuse, Herbert. The Problem of Social Change in the Technological Society in Towards a Critical Theory of Society, Douglas Kellner (ed.) London and New York: Routledge Press, 1961 [2001]
Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels. Selected Works, 2 Volumes, Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House, 1962
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Thus Spoke Zarathustra. In The Portable Nietzsche. Tr. Walter Kaufmann. New York: Viking Press, 1975 [1883-1891]
Queirós, António. A new alliance, environnemental tourisme and cultural landscape. In Landscape and Imagination, Towards a new baseline for education in a changing world. Paysage et Invention. Evolution des enseignements dans un monde en transition. UNISCAPE, Bandecchi&Vivaldi, Florence, 2013
Queirós, António. Cultural agents of change and the sunset of environmental services. The economy and ecology of heathlands. Published by Alterra (Wageningen-UR (University and Research Centre). Neederland, 2013
Queirós, António. A Ética da Terra e as suas Raízes na Filosofia e na Poética da Natureza, in Éticas e Políticas Ambientais.  CFUL,SEA, 2004
Queirós, António. A Representação da Natureza e do Ambiente na Cultura Artística e Científica da Geração de 70. Doctoral thesis in philosophy of science. Center of Philosophy of the University of Lisbon. National Library, 2003
Queirós, António. The dawning  of the Environmental Ethics in the 21st century,  XXIII World Congress of Philosophy, Athens, 2013. Acessed http://philoetichal.blogspot.pt/. 30.06.2015
Quental, Antero. A Filosofia da Natureza dos Naturalistas in Obras Completas de Antero de Quental, Filosofia_III, Organização, Introdução e Notas de Joel Serrão. Universidade dos Açores. Lisboa: Edit. Comunicação, 1991
Quental, Antero. Tendências Gerais da Filosofia na Segunda Metade do Século XIX. Lisboa: Editorial Comunicação, 1989
Reagan, Tom, and Singer, Peter. Animal Rights and Human Obligations. Prentice Hall, New Jersey, 1989.
Ricoeur, Paul. Oneself as Another. Tr. Kathleen Blamey. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992
Sartre, Jean Paul. Existentialism is a Humanism. Tr. Carol Macomber. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2007 [1946]
Sena, Jorge. “Letter to my kids, about the shootings of Goya”. “Peace.” In Trinta Anos de Poesia. Lisboa: Edições 70, 1984
Singer, Peter. Ética Prática, Editora Martins Fontes, São Paulo, 1993
Spinoza, Baruch. Digital and multilingual publication of Spinoza's Ethics http://www.ethicadb.org/index.php?p=&lanid=3&lg=en&ftop=488px. Acessed 30.06.2015
Soromenho-Marques, Viriato. The cosmology of the eternal recurrence, in Thinking the Portuguese culture-tribute to Francisco da Gama Caeiro, ed. Joaquim Gonçalves Cerqueira, Lisbon, Editions Colibri and Department of Philosophy, Faculty of Arts, University of Lisbon, 1993
Strauss, Lévy. Race et Histoire. Paris, UNESCO. 1952
Reeves, Hubert. Les Dernières nouvelles du cosmos. Éditions du Seuil : Paris, 2002
UNCHE, 1972. Action Plan for the Human Environment. B.5. Development and Environment. United Nations Conference on the Human Environment A/CONF.48/14/Rev.1 -June 1972 Stockholm, Sweden
Rolston III, Holmes. Philosophy Gone Wild. Bufalo, Nova York, Prometheus Books, 1986.
Universal Declaration of Human Rights, adopted by the UN in December 10, 1948 (A/RES/217). http://www.un.org/en/documents/udhr/
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophical Investigations, translated by G.E.M. Anscombe, Basil Blackwell, Oxford 1963


[1] Cristina Beckert, “Ethics”, page 90.
[2] Descartes travel around the courts of Central and Northern Europe, in the middle of the “Thirty Years  War”, as professor, scientist and military; contributing to the ideological combat against scholastic and to emerge a new scientific epistemology, such as the birth of a new economic and political regime. In 1643, the University of Utrecht, in their country of refuge, the Netherlands, condemned his philosophy as atheist. In 1667, the Roman Catholic Church placed his works on the index of Forbidden Books.
[3] In 551 B.C., Confucius was born in Zouyi ( Qufu) in the Kingdom Lu and Shandong province, when China was divided by various kingdoms or states who fought among themselves. The population suffered a hard life and society knew the moral degeneration. As if it could then create a well-ordered society, harmonious and happy? These become a pressing issue.
From the three sources of Taoism, we can found as the oldest, the mythical "Yellow Emperor", that have lived between 2697 BC and 2597 BC; the mystical aphorisms book Tao Te Ching (Dao De Jing), attributed to Laozi (Lao Tse), which, according to tradition, was an older contemporary of Confucius (551 BC -479 BC); and the works of the philosopher Zhuangzi (Chuang-Tzu) (369 BC -286 BC).
Almost a thousand years later, St. Augustine was born in Tagaste (Souk-Ahras),  in the year 354,  in Algeria; died on August 28, 430 in Hipona, today Annaba,  Algeria, after writing De Civitate Dei, “The City of God”, among the ruins of the Western Roman Empire; their thought belongs to the field of philosophy-theology of Creation and to the Christological finalism of Celestial City; that philosophy-theology  is  critique of  Neo-Platonism concerning the nature of the soul… but also  proclaims a  political  polemic against those that attributed to the abandonment of the ancient cults and the adoption of Christianity as religion of the Empire, the transcendental cause of its decline and fall.
[4]  Antero de Quental, quoted by Leonardo Coimbra in “O Pensamento Filosófico de Antero de Quental, 1921”. In Antero de Quental, “A Filosofia da Natureza dos Naturalistas, Obras Completas de Antero de Quental, Filosofia:” Organization, Introduction and notes by Joel Serrão,  page 111.
[5] Quoted from our doctoral dissertation (2003).
[6] This means that Antero put his reflection on the philosophy of nature at the most advanced level of development of European thoughts of the epoch concerning the natural sciences and philosophy.
[7] Ernest Haeckel, « Histoire de La Création des Êtres Organisés D'après les Lois Naturelles », pages 29-30. Lamarck postulates the hypothesis that evolutionary change occurs due to the inheritance of acquired characteristics.
[8] Ernest Haëckel, « The Enigmas of the universe », page 13.
[9] Ibidem,  page 13.
[10] Ibidem, page 30.
[11] Ibidem, page 147.
[12] Ibidem, page 147.
[13] Ernest Haeckel, Les Preuves du Transformisme, page 112. Haeckel’s work have a strongly influence in the philosophical thought of Nietzsche. View: Viriato Soromenho-Marques, The cosmology of the eternal recurrence, in Thinking the Portuguese culture-tribute to Francisco da Gama Caeiro, ed. Joaquim Gonçalves Cerqueira, Lisbon, Editions Colibri and Department of Philosophy, Faculty of Arts, University of Lisbon, 1993, pages. 451-462.
[14] Hans Jonas principle, "Act so that the effects of your action are compatible with the permanence of genuine human life". [15] First United Nations  environmental conference, held in Stockholm in 1972.
[16] The concept of landscape has had to be stretched in many directions: from an object to an area, from a visual experience to a multi-sensory one, from natural scenery to the whole range of human-made transformations of nature. This expansion of the idea of landscape is further complicated by the fact that landscapes are never stationary but are constantly in transition.” (Berleant, 2011)
[17] Water, like soil, is a part of the energy circuit. Industry, by polluting water or obstructing it with dams, may exclude the plants and animals necessary to keep energy in circulation…” “Conservation is a state of harmony between men and land…” “The image commonly employed in conservation education is «the balance of nature»...this figure of speech fails to describe accurately what little we know about the land mechanism. A much true image is the one employed in ecology: the biotic pyramid.“ (Aldo Leopold, a Sand Count Almanaque, 1949).
From the reading of this work would break the theorization of bioethics by American oncologist Van Ressenlaer Potter
.[18] Peter Singer,. Ética Prática.
[19] Jorge de Sena, Trinta Anos de Poesia.
[20] Jorge de  Sena,  Trinta Anos de Poesia.
[21] J. Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Moral and Legislation. Chapter I, 1.3.

Sem comentários:

Enviar um comentário